book excerptise:   a book unexamined is not worth having

Syntax: an introduction, Volume 1

Talmy Givon

Givon, Talmy [Givón];

Syntax: an introduction, Volume 1

J. Benjamins, 2nd ed. 2001 (1st: 1984), 500 pages  [gbook]

ISBN 1588110656, 9781588110657

topics: |  language | grammar | linguistics-functional | syntax


Argues for a functionalist view, that is opposed to structuralist models like
Chomsky's.  But Function and structure go hand in hand -
   if structures without function are plainly senseless, functions without
   structures are downright lame.

from Preface

When the first volume was written in the early 1980s, I thought it was
possible to treat grammar responsibly, in terms of both its adaptive
motivation and typological diversity, without an explicit account of the more
formal aspects of syntactic structure. These aspects — constituency,
hierarchy, grammatical relations, clause-union, finiteness and syntactic
control — were matters I took for granted but chose to defer. In retrospect, it
was a bad mistake.  My sins of omission were perhaps understandable as an
over-reaction to the formalism of my early training. But the damage was real
enough.  What I took for granted but for the moment chose to ignore, others
cheerfully discarded.

While the chasm between the formal Generative approach to grammar and the
adaptive perspective I pursue here seems at times unbridgeable, it can be
narrowed down to a relatively small number of issues that are, in principle,
empirical.

ABSTRACTNESS: Does phrase structure pertain only to concrete entities
   (words, phrases, clauses), or also to semantic, pragmatic and sundry
   formal ghosts devoid of surface manifestation?

MORPHOLOGY: Should constituency and hierarchy apply equally to
   grammatical inflections as to lexical words, or does a profound structural
   re-organization occur during grammaticalization?

LINGUA MENTALIS: Is the mental representation of yet-to-be
   communicated thought syntactic, or is grammar a coding function that
   maps cognitive input onto syntactic output?

GRAMMATICAL RELATIONS: Are subject and object universal primes, or are
   they derived from constituency and hierarchy?

IDEALIZATION: Are rules of grammar, or the universals that license
   them, manifestations of some abstract Platonic competence, or are they
   performance constraints on the language processor?

GENERATIVITY: Are rules of grammar 100% rigid, or can they still
   function as neuro-cognitive processing instructions with a certain measure
   of leakage?

EMERGENCE: Are universals of syntax synchronic, or do they constrain
   first and foremost the possible pathways of evolution, acquisition and
   grammaticalization?

Both the extravagantly abstract structures proposed by extreme formalists and
the obsessively concrete structures embraced by extreme functionalists are
due, in large measure, to pre-empirical philosophical predilections. For over
the discordant din loom the twin towers of reductionism — Plato with his
predilection for idealization and abstraction; the Positivists with their
reflexive abhorrence of all invisible mental entities.

Overthe din also looms, still, larger than ever, the paradoxical figure of
Noam Chomsky; who in 1965 licensed semantically-motivated deep structure but
in 1968 and 1970 reined us all in and reaffirmed the Saussurean dogma of
autonomous syntax; who between 1957 and 1965 celebrated the reality of
concrete syntactic structures, but in 1992 decreed them figments of the
methodologist’s imagination.

It is convenient to forget that the 1965-vintage Aspects model did proclaim,
explicitly, the isomorphism between syntactic deep structure and
propositional-semantic function, a dispensation that was tweaked to its
logical conclusion two years later by Ross and Lakoff.

It is just as easy to forget that even the most extravagant mad-hatter
abstractness of Minimalism is still inspired by a germ of perfectly good
intentions — the search for universals that are not about uttered concrete
structures, but about the neuro-cognitive organization that accounts for such
structures.

That the carcasses of perfectly good intentions still litter linguistics’
road to, well, whatever, is a sad legacy of Platonism’s methodological
indifference; in this case, the disdain for the tiresome process of
discovery, a distant echo of Socrates’ frustration with expert
knowledge. From whence flows the reification of competence and the mirage of
generativity. The Devil is, alas, still, in the fine detail.

The research program outlined here pays heed to Chomsky’s exhortation to seek
universal principles, while affirming the mental reality of syntactic
structures. For while not the real end of the theoretical enterprise,
concrete structures are real enough. As theoretical entities, perceived and
produced by the language processor. As methodological entities, grist to the
mill of discovery and theory building.

1: The functional approach to language


Chapter 1: The functional approach to language and the typological approach
to grammar

The history of the functional approach to language:
Edward Sapir:
    Language is a purely human and non-instinctive method of communicating
ideas, emotions and desires by means of a system of voluntarily produced
symbols... " [Sapir, Language, 1921 p.8]
    Hence we have no recourse but to accept lg as a fully formed functional
system witin man's psyche or "spiritual" constitution.  We cannot define it
as an entity in psycho-physical terms alone, however much the psycho-physical
basis is essential to its functioning. p.10-11, Language

Otto Jespersen:
    The essence of lg is human activity -- activity on the part of one
    individual to make himself understood by another, activity on the part of
    the other to understand what was in the mind of the first... "
    		[Jaspersen The philosophy of grammar 1934, p.17)

George Zipf:
    language is primarily a representation of experience.  It may repr
    experience as [in an account of a football game].  Or it may repr
    tendencies to act representative of potential activity, such as an
    oration to persuade others to modify their behaviour... a function of the
    linguistic representation is to preserve or restore equilibrium.  This
    equilibrm may be of two types: a) inter-personal, and b)
    intrapersonal...
		Zipf, The psycho-biology of language, 1935, p.294-5

Ultimately, however, the best point of departure for functionalism is to be
found in biology, which has been profoundly functionalist for 2K years.
Aristotle ~single-handedly dislodged the two structuralist schools that had
dominated Greek biological thought up to his time.  Both schools sought to
understand live organisms componentially, the way they did inorganic matter.
Thus Empedocles proposed to explain organisms by their component elements.
While Democritus opted for understanding organisms through their compoent
parts, or structure.

In his De Partibus Animalium, Aristotle first argues against Empedocles'
elemental approach, pointing out the relevance of histological and anatomical
structure:

      "... But if men and animals are natural phenomena, then natural
      philosophers must take into consideration not merely the ultimate
      substances of which they are made, but also flesh, bone, blood and all
      the other homogeneous parts; not only these but also the heterogeneous
      parts, such as face, hand, foot...  Does configuration and color
      constitute the essence of the various animals and their several parts?
      ... No hand of bronze or wood or constituted in any but the appropriate
      way can possibly be a hand in more than a name.  For like a physician
      in a painting, or like a flute in a sculpture, it will be unable to do
      the _office which that name implies..." [McKeon ed. 1941 p.647]

      "... if a piece of wood is to be split with an axe, the axe must of
      necessity be hard; and indeed if hard, it must of necessity be made of
      bronze or iron.  Now exactly in the same way the body, which like the
      axe is an instrument - for both the body as a whole and its several
      parts individually have definite operations for which they are made;
      just in the same way, I say, the body if it is to do its work, must
      of nec be of such andd such character... " [650]

[Arbitrariness of grammar - rejected by Givon.

Aristotle's doctrine of the arbitrariness of the linguistic sign --
thus the arbitrariness of cross-language diversity -- refers only to the
coding of concepts by words.  Latter-day structuralists unreflectively
extended the arbitrariness doctrine to grammar.
]

In the early 20th c. structuralism re-surfaced in the nascent social
sciences.  To the infant disciplines of psychology, anthropology and
linguistics, two towering exponents of logical positivist philo of sci,
Russell and Carnap - sold the deceptive analogy of physics.  from Carnap's reflections:

    The thesis of physicalism as orig accepted in the Vienna Circle, says
    roughly : Every concept of the lg of sci can be explicitly defined in
    terms of observables;  therefore every sentence of the lg of S is
    translatable into a sentence concerning observable properties... " [Philo
    of R Carnap 1963, p. 59]

CHOMSKY's ASPECT

The functional approach to grammar pursued here owes its direct descent,
somewhat paradoxically, to Chomsky's fatal indecision, in his
Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (1965) about the relationship between
syntax and meaning.  While insisting on the arbitrariness and autonomy of
grammar, Chomsky nonetheless conceded that syntactic deep structuure (in
our terms here, the structure of simple clauses) was isomorphic to
propositional meaning (his logical structure).  This crypto-functionalist
lapse, soon discarded by Chomsky himself, was embraced by Ross and Lakoff
(1967) and others who under the banner of Generative Semantics, spurned the
dogma of autonomous syntax.

Early functionalism focus on the reln between grammar and propositional
semantics:
[Chafe 70; Lakoff 70; Foley vanValin 84; Langacker 87,90]
But the realization that the bulk of the machinery of grammar was deployed in
the service of discourse pragmatics did not lag far behind
[Givon 79; Chafe 1980, 1994; Hopper ed. 1982; Tomlin ed 1987]

Contents

Chapter 1 : functional approach to language and typological approach to grammar

1.1 Perspective							1
  1.1.1 Antecedence							1
  1.1.2 Structuralism							4
  1.1.3 Direct descent						7
1.2 The role of grammar in human information processing		7
  1.2.1 The cognitive representation system				7
  1.2.2 Peripheral sensory-motor codes				11
  1.2.3 The grammatical code						11
1.3 Grammatical vs. pre-grammatical communication			13
1.4 The limits of conscious reflection				16
1.5 The theme-and-variation approach to syntax			18
1.6 The typological approach to grammar: Functional domains,
    cross-language diversity and universals				20
  1.6.1 The functional basis of grammatical typology			20
  1.6.2 The diachronic underpinnings of grammatical typology		23
  1.6.3 Typology and universals of grammar				24
  1.6.4 Ranges of typological variation				25
1.7 Generativity and variation					26
  1.7.1 The bounds of rule-governedness				26
  1.7.2 Categories, continua and prototypes				28
1.8 Iconicity, naturalness and markedness				34
  1.8.1 Iconicity vs. arbitrariness					34
  1.8.2 Markedness, complexity and frequency				37
1.9 On the use, and uses, of this book				41

Chapter 2 : % The lexicon: Words and morphemes 43

2.1 Preliminaries							43
  2.1.1 Recapitulation: Meaning, information, discourse		43
  2.1.2 Semantic features and semantic fields				43
2.2 Lexical vs. grammatical vocabulary				44
  2.2.1 Words and morphemes						44
  2.2.2 Morphemic status, morphotactics, and writing systems		48
2.3 Majorle xical word-classes					49
  2.3.1 Membership criteria						49
  2.3.2 Pragmatic limits of semantic taxonomies			50
  2.3.3 Semantic criteria: An overview				50
  2.3.4 Morphotactics: Affixes, clitics and inflections		54
2.4 Nouns								55
  2.4.1 Semantic characterization					55
  2.4.2 Syntactic characteristics					59
  2.4.3 Morphological characteristics					60
2.5 Verb s								69
  2.5.1 Semantic characterization					69
  2.5.2 Syntactic characterization					69
  2.5.3 Morphological characterization				69
2.6 Adjectives							81
  2.6.1 Semantic characterization					81
  2.6.2 Syntactic characterization					84
  2.6.3 Morphological characteristics					85
2.7 Adverbs								87
  2.7.1 Preamble							87
  2.7.2 Semantic classification					88
2.8 Minor word classes						94
  2.8.1 Preamble							94
  2.8.2 Adpositions							95
  2.8.3 Determiners							97
  2.8.4 Independent subject and object pronouns			99
  2.8.5 Inter-clausal connectives					99
  2.8.6 Quantifiers, numerals and ordinals				100
  2.8.7 Auxiliary verbs						102
  2.8.8 Interjections							102

Chapter 3 : Simple verbal clauses and argument structure 105

3.1 Preliminaries							105
  3.1.1 Orientation							105
  3.1.2 States, events, and actions					106
  3.1.3 Semantic roles						106
  3.1.4 Grammatical relations						108
  3.1.5 Transitivity							109
3.2 Phrase structure and tree diagrams				110
  3.2.1 What the formalism is good for				110
  3.2.2 What the formalism is not good for				114
3.3 The classification of verbs and simple clauses			118
  3.3.1 Dummy-subject verbs						118
  3.3.2 Copularc lauses and copularv erbs				120
  3.3.3 Simple intransitive verbs					125
  3.3.4 Simple transitive verbs					126
  3.3.5 Intransitive verbs with an indirect object			136
  3.3.6 Bi-transitive verbs						141
  3.3.7 Verbs with clausal (verbal) complements			149
  3.3.8 Multiple membership in verb classes				160
3.4 Optional participant case-roles					161
3.5 Distributed lexical verbs						162
  3.5.1 Complex predicates distributed across the clause		163
  3.5.2 Multiple stems distributed across the verbal word		167

Chapter 4 : Grammatical relations and case-marking systems 173

4.1 Orientation							173
4.2 Semantic roles vs. grammatical relations: The dissociation test	173
4.3 Formal properties of grammatical relations			175
  4.3.1 Overt coding properties					175
  4.3.2 Behavior-and-control properties				177
  4.3.3 Universality and variation: The prototype approach to
  	grammatical relations						194
  4.3.4 Functional correlates of grammatical relations		195
4.4 The typology of case-marking systems				197
  4.4.1 Preliminaries							197
  4.4.2 Topicality and grammatical relations				198
  4.4.3 Majort ypes of case-marking systems				200
4.5 The typology of direct objects					219
  4.5.1 Overt coding properties: Degree of grammaticalization		219
  4.5.2 Morphological promotion-to-DO and the topicality hierarchy	220
  4.5.3 Promotion to DO and verb-coding of semantic roles		225
4.6 Serial verbs, case-marking and grammatical relations		227
4.7 Verb-coding of case-roles						230

Chapter 5: Word order p.233

5.1 Preliminaries							233
5.2 Scalarity, consistency and purity of types			234
5.3 Rigid word-order types						235
  5.3.1 Rigid word-order in simple (main) clauses			235
  5.3.2 Rigid word-order in the noun phrase				242
5.4 Mixed word-orders							246
  5.4.1 Mixed clausal order						246
  5.4.2 Mixed word-order in the NP					254
5.5 Word-order and bound morphology					260
  5.5.1 Reorientation							260
  5.5.2 Case-marking morphology on nouns or NPs			260
  5.5.3 Tense-aspect-modal morphology					263
  5.5.4 Negation morphemes						267
5.6 Flexible word-order						270
  5.6.1 Reorientation							270
  5.6.2 Types of flexible-order languages				271
  5.6.3 The pragmatics of word-order flexibility			277
5.7 So-called non-configurationality					279

Chapter 6: Tense, aspect and modality I: Functional organization 85

6.1 Introduction							285
6.2 Tense								285
6.3 Aspect								287
  6.3.1 Perfectivity: boundedness and duration			287
  6.3.2 Perfective vs. imperfective					288
  6.3.3 The perfect							293
  6.3.4 The immediate aspect: Remote vs. vivid			297
6.4 Modality and mood							300
  6.4.1 Preamble: Propositional modalities				300
  6.4.2 Epistemic modalities						301
  6.4.3 The distribution of modality in grammar			302
  6.4.4 Irrealis and the subjunctive mood8				312
  6.4.5 Evidentiality and epistemic space				326
6.5 Communicative and cognitive aspects of tense, aspectand modality	329
  6.5.1 Markedness							329
  6.5.2 Frequency text-distribution					330
  6.5.3 Cognitive considerations					332
  6.5.4 The discourse correlates of aspect: Perfective/imperfective vs.
  	simultaneous/sequential						333

Chapter 7 : Tense, aspect and modality II: Typological organization 337

7.1 Reorientation							337
7.2 The Creole prototype						338
7.3 T-A-M auxiliaries and their grammaticalization			340
7.4 The expansion of tense						341
7.5 The scope-of-assertion aspect					343
7.6 Perfective/imperfective-based systems				345
7.7 A four-way dichotomy						348
7.8 The conflation of perfect, durative and immediate			352
7.9 The grammaticalization of modality				355
  7.9.1 Marking presupposed vs. asserted information			355
  7.9.2 Split vs. uniform marking of irrealis				358
  7.9.3 Unified vs. split subjunctive					360
  7.9.4 The use of perfective markers in subjunctive forms		362
7.10 The grammaticalization of evidentiality				366
7.11 Primary vs. secondary grammaticalization of T-A-M		366

Chapter 8 : Negation 369

8.1 The multiple facets of negation					369
  8.1.1 Negation and propositional logic				369
  8.1.2 Negation and subjective certainty				370
  8.1.3 The communicative pragmatics of negation			370
  8.1.4 Negation as a speech-act					372
8.2 The cognitive status of negation					372
  8.2.1 Change vs. stasis						372
  8.2.2 The ontology of negative events				373
  8.2.3 The ontology of negative states				375
8.3 Negation and social interaction					376
8.4 The scope of negation						378
  8.4.1 Presupposition, assertion and negation			378
  8.4.2 Negation and contrastive focus				380
  8.4.3 Negation and optional constituents				381
8.5 The morpho-syntactic typology of VP negation			382
  8.5.1 Grammaticalization of negation markers			382
  8.5.2 De-verbal negation markers					382
  8.5.3 De-nominal negation markers					383
  8.5.4 Negation and word-order					385
8.6 Further topics in the syntax of negation				386
  8.6.1 The coding of negative scope					386
  8.6.2 Diverse negation markers across grammatical contexts		388
  8.6.3 Emphatic orNP negation					392
  8.6.4 Negation in main vs. complement clauses			393
  8.6.5 Depth of embedding: Syntactic, morphological, and
	inherent (‘lexical’) negation					395
  8.6.6 Negative polarity and levels of negation			396

Chapter 9 : Referential coherence I: Pronouns and grammatical agreement

9.1 Introduction							399
9.2 The semantic organization of pronominal paradigms			400
  9.2.1 Pronominal classificatory features				400
  9.2.2 Initial selected examples					401
9.3 Pronoun and grammatical agreement					407
  9.3.1 Optional clitic anaphoric pronouns (Ute)			407
  9.3.2 Pronominal agreement on the verb				408
9.4 The implicational hierarchies of pronominal agreement		416
9.5 Foundations of the grammar anaphoric reference			417
  9.5.1 Preamble							417
  9.5.2 Anaphoric zero vs. unstressed anaphoric pronouns		417
  9.5.3 Anaphoric vs. stressed independent pronouns			418
  9.5.4 Pronouns and zero anaphors vs. definite full-NPs		419
9.6 Explaining the rise of pronominal agreement			420
9.7 Head-modifierag reement in the noun phrase			426
9.8 Multiple functions of grammatical agreement			430
  9.8.1 Verb-type and transitivity (Melanesian Pidgin)		430
  9.8.2 Marking direct vs. indirect objects (KinyaRwanda, Lunda)	431
  9.8.3 Marking topical objects (Amharic, Machiguenga)		432
  9.8.4 Marking definite objects (Swahili)				433
  9.8.5 Marking main vs. subordinate clauses (Bemba)			433
  9.8.6 Marking existential-presentative clauses (KinyaRwanda)	433
  9.8.7 Binding NP constituents together				434
9.9 Indefinite and non-referring pronouns				434

Chapter 10: Referential coherence II: Reference and definiteness

10.1 Introduction							437
10.2 Reference							437
  10.2.1 The RealWorld vs. the Universe of Discourse			437
  10.2.2 Referential intent						439
  10.2.3 The universal quantifier and non-reference			439
10.3 The semantics of indefinite reference4				440
  10.3.1 Referential opacity						441
  10.3.2 Reference and propositional modalities			441
  10.3.3 Gradations of referentiality					449
10.4 Grammatical marking of indefinite reference			450
  10.4.1 Preamble							450
  10.4.2 The numeral ‘one’ as reference marker			450
  10.4.3 The demonstrative ‘this’ as reference marker			452
  10.4.4 Noun classifiers and reference markers			453
  10.4.5 Grammatical devices that mark non-reference			454
  10.5 The pragmatics of indefinite reference: Denotation vs.
	 topicality							455
10.6 Definiteness							459
  10.6.1 Definiteness and anaphoric reference				459
  10.6.2 Grounding referents to the shared current speech
  situation (working memory, current attention focus)			460
  10.6.3 Grounding to shared generic-lexical knowledge (permanent
  semantic memory)							460
  10.6.4 Anaphoric grounding to the shared current text (long-term
  episodic memory)							462
  10.6.5 Proper names and global access				464
  10.6.6 Generic subjects						465
  10.6.7 Gradation of definite description				467
10.7 Grammatical marking of definite NPs				468
  10.7.1 Distal demonstratives					468
  10.7.2 Noun classifiers						469
  10.7.3 Definite-accusative markers					470
  10.7.4 Direct object and dative shifting				471
  10.7.5 Topicalization and definiteness				472
  10.7.6 Pronominal object agreement					473
  10.7.7 Definiteness, reference and case-roles			473
10.8 The grammar of referential coherence as mental processing
     instructions							474
Bibliography								479
Index									493

Why "an introduction"?

These two volumes are introductory in two distinct senses. First, they start
from zero and assume no priorkno wledge of syntax, howeverbr iskly they may
then proceed. Second, they remain primarily a survey of the phenomenology of
grammar. In the process, they introduce the reader first to concrete
morpho-syntactic structures and their semantic and pragmatic correlates. They
then map out the likely bounds of cross-language typological variability. Out
of this primal phenomenology emerge, gradually, some of the universal
principles that govern both the functional and structural organization of
grammar.  Complex as this enterprise may seem, it is but a preliminary to the
real task, that of elaborating the universal principles that govern the
emergence of grammar as a language processor — in evolution, in development, in
diachrony.

I would like to dedicate these volumes to an old friend whose work at times
seems just as paradoxical as my own; who shares both my passion for the
incredible diversity of languages and my faith in the ultimate commonality of
language; Ken Hale. Abrazos, Jefe.

				To Ken Hale,
			   a linguist’s linguist,
			     a cowboy’s cowboy.


amitabha mukerjee (mukerjee [at-symbol] gmail.com) 2011 Feb 17